Believe It or Not: On Multiplying Classes of Belief-like States

Authors

  • James Robert Thompson Mississippi State University

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.12697/spe.2016.9.1.04

Keywords:

belief, alief, folk psychology

Abstract

This paper explores whether it is justified to add any new taxa concerning informational states to our psychological taxonomy. Such exploration will not lead to a straightforward decision between remaining steadfast with the taxonomic status quo and adding only one new taxon. A careful analysis of when one would be warranted in positing a new taxon for informational states will reveal similarly compelling reasons to posit all sorts of additional taxa. As an antidote to such proliferation, I suggest a reinforcement of traditional taxonomies of the mental by allowing belief and a range of extant taxa to play their requisite explanatory roles, thereby obviating the need for the postulation of any novel taxa.

Author Biography

James Robert Thompson, Mississippi State University

Department of Philosophy and Religion

Associate Professor

References

Albahari, M. (2013). Alief or belief? A contextual approach to belief ascription. Philosophical Studies. http://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0122-x

Baillargeon, R., Scott, R. M., & He, Z. (2010). False-belief understanding in infants. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14(3), 110-118. http://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2009.12.006

Bortolotti, L. (2010). Delusions and other irrational beliefs. New York: Oxford University Press.

Bratman, M. (1992). Practical reasoning and acceptance in a context. Mind, 10 1-15.

Brownstein, M., & Madva, A. (2012). The normativity of automaticity. Mind & Language, 27(4), 410-434. http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0017.2012.01450.x

Caron, A. J. (2009). Comprehension of the representational mind in infancy. Developmental Review, 2 69-95. http://doi.org/10.1016/j.dr.2009.04.002

Carpenter, M., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2002). A new false belief test for 36-month-olds. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 20(3), 393-420. http://doi.org/10.1348/026151002320620316

Carruthers, P. (2006). The architecture of the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Carruthers, P. (2011). The opacity of mind: An integrative theory of self-knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Carruthers, P. (2013). Mindreading in infancy. Mind & Language, 28(2), 141-172. http://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12014

Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. The Journal of Philosophy, 78(2), 67-90. http://doi.org/10.2307/2025900

Clements, W. A., & Perner, J. (1994). Implicit understanding of belief. Cognitive Development, 9(4), 377-395.

Cohen, L. J. (1989). Belief and acceptance. Mind, 9 367-389.

Cohen, L. J. (1992). An essay on belief and acceptance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Currie, G., & Ichino, A. (2012). Aliefs don’t exist, though some of their relatives do. Analysis, 72(4), 788-798. http://doi.org/10.1093/analys/ans088

Davies, M. (1989). Tacit knowledge and subdoxastic states. In A. George (Ed.), Reflections on Chomsky (pp. 131-152). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

Dennett, D. C. (1978). How to change your mind. In Brainstorms (pp. 300-309). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Doggett, T. (2012). Some questions for Tamar Szabo Gendler. Analysis, 72(4), 764-774. http://doi.org/10.1093/analys/ans090

Egan, A. (2008). Seeing and believing: perception, belief formation and the divided mind. Philosophical Studies, 140(1), 47-63. http://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-008-9225-1

Egan, A. (2011). Comments on Gendler’s “The epistemic costs of implicit bias.” Philosophical Studies, 156(1), 65-79. http://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-011-9803-5

Engel, P. (2012). Trust and the doxastic family. Philosophical Studies, 161(1), 17-26. http://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9946-z

Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. (J. McDowell, Ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Evans, G. (1985). Semantic theory and tacit knowledge. In Collected Papers. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind: An essay on faculty psychology. Cambridge: MIT Press.

Fodor, J. A. (2000). The mind doesn’t work that way: The scope and limits of computational psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Gendler, T. S. (2008a). Alief and belief. Journal of Philosophy, 10 634-663.

Gendler, T. S. (2008b). Alief in action (and reaction). Mind & Language, 23(5), 552-585. http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0017.2008.00352.x

Gendler, T. S. (2011). On the epistemic costs of implicit bias. Philosophical Studies, 156(1), 33-63. http://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-011-9801-7

Gendler, T. S. (2012). Between reason and reflex: Response to commentators. Analysis, 72(4), 799-811. http://doi.org/10.1093/analys/ans089

Gertler, B. (2011). Self-knowledge and the transparency of belief. In A. Hatzimoysis (Ed.), Self-knowledge (pp. 125-145). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Gigerenzer, G. (2009). Surrogates for a theory. APS Observer, 2 21-22.

Greco, D. (2014). A puzzle about epistemic akrasia. Philosophical Studies, 167(2), 201-219. http://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-0085-3

Hirstein, W. (2005). Brain fiction: Self-deception and the riddle of confabulation. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Horowitz, S. (2013). Epistemic akrasia. Nous. Retrieved from http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12026/full

Huddleston, A. (2012). Naughty beliefs. Philosophical Studies, 160(2), 209-222. http://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-011-9714-5

Hutto, D. D. (2008). Folk psychological narratives: The sociological basis of understanding reasons. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Keren, G., & Schul, Y. (2009). Two is not always better than one. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 533-550.

Kriegel, U. (2012). Moral motivation, moral phenomenology, and the alief/belief distinction. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90(3), 469-486. http://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2011.607464

Kung, P. (2012). Review of “Intuition, Imagination, and Philosophical Methodology.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90(4), 806-809. http://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2012.717954

Kwong, J. (2012). Resisting aliefs: Gendler on belief-discordant behaviors. Philosophical Psychology, 25(1), 77-91.

Lehrer, K. (1990). Metamind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Lehrer, K. (2000). Belief and acceptance revisited. In P. Engel (Ed.), Believing and accepting (pp. 209-220). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Lewis, D. (1982). Logic for equivocators. Nous, 16(3), 431-441. http://doi.org/10.2307/2216219

Low, J., & Wang, B. (2011). On the long road to mentalism in children’s spontaneous false-belief understanding: Are we there yet? Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2(3), 411-428. http://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-011-0067-y

Luo, Y. (2011). Do 10-month-old infants understand others’ false beliefs? Cognition, 12 289-298. http://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2011.07.011

Lycan, W. (1986). Tacit belief. In R. Bogdan (Ed.), Belief: Form, content, and function (pp. 61-82). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Mandelbaum, E. (2013). Against alief. Philosophical Studies, 165(1), 197-211. http://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9930-7

Mandelbaum, E. (2014). The automatic and the ballistic: Modularity beyond perceptual processes. Philosophical Psychology, 1-10. http://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2014.950217

Mandelbaum, E. (2015). Attitude, inference, association: On the propositional structure of implicit bias. Nous, n/a-n/a. http://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12089

Miller, A. (1997). Tacit knowledge. In B. Hale & C. Wright (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of language. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

Nagel, J. (2012). Gendler on alief. Analysis, 72(4), 774-788. http://doi.org/10.1093/analys/ans091

Onishi, K. H., & Baillargeon, R. (2005). Do 15-month-old infants understand false beliefs? Science, 30 255-258. http://doi.org/10.1126/science.1107621

Penn, D. C., Holyoak, K. J., & Povenelli, D. (2008). Darwin’s mistake: Explaining the discontinuity between human and nonhuman minds. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3 109-78.

Perner, J. (2010). Who took the cog out of cognitive science? Mentalism in an era of anti-cognitivism. In P. Frensch & R. Schwarzer (Eds.), Cognition and neuropsychology: International perspectives on psychological science (Vol. pp. 241-261). Hove, UK: Psychology Press.

Poland, J., & Graham, G. (Eds.). (2011). Addiction and responsibility. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Retrieved from http://site.ebrary.com/id/10479194

Povinelli, D. J., & Vonk, J. (2004). We don’t need a microscope to explore the chimpanzee’s mind. Mind & Language, 1 1-28. http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0017.2004.00244.x

Schwitzgebel, E. (2002). A phenomenal, dispositional account of belief. Nous, 36(2), 249-275. http://doi.org/10.1111/1468-0068.00370

Schwitzgebel, E. (2010). Acting contrary to our professed beliefs, or the gulf between occurrent judgment and dispositional belief. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 91(4), 531-553. http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0114.2010.01381.x

Schwitzgebel, E. (2011). Belief. In E. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition).

Simons, D. J., & Rensink, R. A. (2005). Change blindness: past, present, and future. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9(1), 16-20. http://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2004.11.006

Sloman, S. A. (1996). The empirical case for two systems of reasoning. Psychological Bulletin, 11 3-22. http://doi.org/10.1037/0033-2909.119.1.3

Southgate, V., Chevallier, C., & Csibra, G. (2010). Seventeen-month-olds appeal to false beliefs to interpret others’ referential communication. Developmental Science, 13(6), 907-912. http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-7687.2009.00946.x

Southgate, V., Senju, A., & Csibra, G. (2007). Action anticipation through attribution of false belief by 2-year-olds. Psychological Science, 1 587-592. http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9280.2007.01944.x

Stalnaker, R. (1984). Inquiry. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Stich, S. P. (1978). Beliefs and subdoxastic states. Philosophy of Science, 45(4), 499-518. http://doi.org/10.2307/186966

Stich, S. P. (1983). From folk psychology to cognitive science: The case against belief. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Surian, L., Caldi, S., & Sperber, D. (2007). Attribution of beliefs by 13-month-old infants. Psychological Science, 18(7), 580-586.

Thompson, J. R. (2014). Signature limits in mindreading systems. Cognitive Science, 38(7), 1432-1455. http://doi.org/10.1111/cogs.12117

Weiskrantz, L. (1986). Blindsight: A case study and implications. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Wellman, H. M., Cross, D., & Watson, J. (2001). Meta-analysis of theory-of-mind development: The truth about false belief. Child Development, 7 655-684. http://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8624.00304

Wimmer, H., & Perner, J. (1983). Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children’s understanding of deception. Cognition, 1 103-128. http://doi.org/10.1016/0010-0277(83)90004-5

Zahavi, D. (2011). Empathy and direct social perception: A phenomenological proposal. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2(3), 541-558. http://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-011-0070-3

Downloads

Published

2017-02-15

How to Cite

Thompson, J. R. (2017). Believe It or Not: On Multiplying Classes of Belief-like States. Studia Philosophica Estonica, 9(1), 79–110. https://doi.org/10.12697/spe.2016.9.1.04